Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Our “Barbarians” at the Gate: On the Undercriminalized Citizenship Deprivation as a Counterterrorism Tool

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Germany is joining a long list of European democracies that have modified or expressed a willingness to modify their citizenship laws to denationalize first and then prevent the return of or expel those citizens accused of having participated in terrorist activities abroad. The formal labelling of citizenship deprivation as an administrative measure outside the scope of criminal justice has prevented scholars of criminal law from undertaking a thorough scrutiny of its legitimacy. In this paper I seek to fill this gap. Specifically, after demonstrating why deprivation of citizenship is a measure of a criminal nature, I argue against its legitimacy, either as a punishment or as a risk-based measure. Instead I propose that we should understand citizenship deprivation as a paradigmatic response from an illegitimate enemy criminal law. Notwithstanding the foregoing, I claim that states that choose to denationalize terrorists should do it within the framework of a process with the highest (criminal procedural) guarantees.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I take the example from Tripkovic (2019, 90–91).

  2. Duff (2018, 138).

  3. In this article, I use citizenship “denationalization/deprivation/withdrawal” indistinctly. I would like to thank the anonymous reviewer from Criminal Law and Philosophy who made me realize in time that the term “expatriation” has a wider meaning than just the forcible permanent removal of citizenship, namely, the use of force or law to remove people from their own countries. I also use the notions of citizenship and nationality in an equivalent manner, although conceptually they do not necessarily overlap. For discussion, see Gibney (2017, 361).

  4. For a general overview, see Gibney (2013a, 221–223), (2017, 364–367), Kingston (2005).

  5. For views of this kind, see Macklin (2014, 1–3), Zedner (2019a).

  6. On this trend, see, e.g., Cloots (2017, 57–58), Pillai/Williams (2017, 522), Esbrook (2016, 1275–1276). On the use of immigration and citizenship law as a tool of counterterrorism, see also Ashworth/Zedner (2014, 242–247), Zedner (2016a, 4–8), Zedner (2019b).

  7. Despite the fact that the United Kingdom is a signatory to the 1961 UN Convention on the Reduction of Statelessness. For more on this, see Zedner (2016a, 8–12).

  8. For a general overview, see Shachar (2012), and Gibney (2017, 376–377), who rightly warns that denationalization fits well with the modern meritocratic view of citizenship as a privilege, one conditional upon conformity with standards of behaviour or values.

  9. See, e.g., Dubber (2010) or Zedner (2013).

  10. See, e.g., Bennett (2016, 411–425), or Tripkovic (2019). On the surreptitious revival of “civil death” in the form of aggregated collateral consequences (disenfranchisement, criminal registration and community notification requirements, ineligibility to live, work, etc.), see Chin (2012) and Kleinfeld (2016, 966–971).

  11. Something different happens in the Anglophone discussion. See, e.g., Lavi (2011, 2010), Gross (2003), Zaibert (2008).

  12. This point of view is clear in the German discussion: although Art. 16 of the Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany prohibits the “deprivation” (Entzug) of citizenship, its loss or forfeiture (Verlust) is allowed; thus, the denationalization of a terrorist, like that of a soldier who joins foreign troops, would not be a (criminal) sanction but the declaration of the new status freely configured by the affected person. The German Constitutional Court distinguishes between the two concepts on the basis of the avoidability of the behaviour that determines it. On this, see Cloots (2017, 60–63). This distinction obscures the fact that, ultimately, the state withdraws the citizenship—also against the will of the affected party.

  13. This is the case, for example, in the United Kingdom, Austria, the Netherlands, and Germany.

  14. Steiker (1998, 777).

  15. Although there are several recognized causes of loss of nationality in citizenship law (e.g., fraudulent acquisition, voluntary renunciation, or incorporation into foreign troops), from now on I am interested only in the forced withdrawal by the state of the citizenship of those who have participated in terrorist activities. Nor do I deal here with cases in which a terrorist who has no material link (genuine connection) with the state in question is deprived of his nationality. See on this below n. 64.

  16. See the discussion in Ball (2011, 119–135).

  17. Joppke (2016, 734) claims that the “decoupling of citizenship stripping from penal law is a deliberate measure to sidestep the higher burdens of proof that the state meets in criminal law”. For a similar approach, see also Ashworth/Zedner (2010, 77), Zedner (2007, 264–273).

  18. For a defence on the pragmatic approach in defining “criminal” law, see Chiao (2019, 182–210), Ball (2011, 119–135), or Ristroph (2008, 1394–1406).

  19. To establish a test for determining the meaning of a “criminal charge”, three criteria were developed by the Strasbourg Court in the leading case of Engel [Engel v Netherlands (1979–1980) 1 EHRR 647]: (a) the formal label, which serves only as a starting point; (b) the nature of the offence and the proceeding to which it gives rise; c) and the severity of the penalty. For discussion on this “anti-subversion doctrine”, see, e.g., Trechsel (2005, 14–30).

  20. On the punitive rationale of the citizenship deprivation, see Gross (2003, 58), Joppke (2016, 734–735), Lavi (2011, 788–789), Zaibert (2008, 386), or Cheh (1991, 1363): formal labelling is irrelevant when “the punishment imposed so dramatically expresses societal disapproval that its imposition only can be legitimated through the ceremony of a criminal conviction”. That is the case of execution, incarceration, and loss of citizenship.

  21. For essential reading on this phenomenon and its perils, see Ashworth/Zedner (2010). They allude to undercriminalization as the phenomenon of regulating coercive measures of a criminal nature outside the criminal sphere to avoid the procedural protections of criminal law. On this, see also Zedner (2016b).

  22. Duff (2009, 13).

  23. The penal risk-based measure is necessarily post-criminal. The previous crime is not its foundation, as it is based solely upon a prediction concerning future offences, but its prior commission is a fundamental external limit. On this, see, e.g., Robles Planas (2007, 3–8).

  24. On the (in)compatibility of denationalization with the Engel test, see, e.g., Cloots (2017, 81–82).

  25. For a related discussion, see Mantu (2015, 298–310).

  26. See, e.g., Cancio Meliá/Petzsche (2013, 87–92).

  27. For more detail on this, see Zedner (2019a, 327, 342).

  28. See Cheh (1991, 1352–1353, 1363), Greco (2015, 683–684).

  29. For further discussion, see Gibney (2019).

  30. See also Zedner (2016a, 8), and Lenard (2016, 84), who suggests that citizenship deprivation could make the denationalized a potential target of counterterrorist killing operations.

  31. For more on this, see Mantu (2018, 29–31).

  32. Lavi (2011, 795–797). In the same sense, see Gross (2003, 66).

  33. Lavi (2011, 800–801).

  34. Lavi (2011, 805). See also Gross (2003, 60), who also legitimizes criminal denationalization, which nevertheless highlights it deterrence function.

  35. See Scheffler (2006), Cancio Meliá (2011).

  36. Pawlik (2017, 56). See also Duff (2001, 72, 77–79), and Lacey (1988, 171–186).

  37. For a general account on citizens’ criminal law, see Duff (2010, 300–304, 2018, 102–145), and Pawlik (2017, 29–46), with further references.

  38. For this view, see Silva Sánchez (2018, 221–222), Pawlik (2017, 56), Du Bois-Pedain (2017), Duff (2003, 709, 2010, 301).

  39. Duff (2011, 140).

  40. Pawlik (2017, 56), Duff (1998, 256, 2018, 137–142, 192–201). Duff nevertheless understands that this is a question of how inclusive the polity wants to be. In my opinion, however, the very concept of legitimate punishment precludes the possibility of punishing through denationalization: no one should bear a punishment consisting in the definitive loss of citizenship.

  41. Duff (2010, 301). For a similar view, see Cohen (2016).

  42. The same conclusion will also be reached by those who legitimize punishment on the basis of its deterrence function. There is no evidence that citizenship deprivation will deter a person who is willing to die for a cause. See on this Macklin (2018, 171).

  43. See, e.g., Ashworth/Zedner (2010, 61–63), Tripkovic (2019, 61–64).

  44. On this, see Husak (2013).

  45. See, e.g., Husak (2013), Zedner (2016b), and recently Puente Rodríguez (2019, 6–10).

  46. On overprediction and the respect of the human agency on assessing risk-based measures, see, e.g., Von Hirsch/Wasik (1997, 607–608). Specifically, in the context of denationalization, see also Lenard (2016, p. 86).

  47. For a discussion of this point, see Carey (2018, 898). For a general questioning of the preventive effectiveness of the exceptional criminal law against terrorism, see Cancio Meliá (2011, 113–117).

  48. Depending on the destination country, deportation may make it easier for the individual to engage in activities that pose a threat to the community expelling him. For this argument, see Lenard (2016, 85). For alternative proposals to fight terrorism (e.g., passport suspension, temporary exclusion orders, rehabilitation programs, and increased border security), see also Esbrook (2016, 1312–1328, Zedner (2019b, 107–114).

  49. See, e.g., Cohen (2016, 255–256).

  50. Among the many works of Jakobs on this topic, the following are fundamental: Jakobs (2004a), recently (2019). For an English-language introduction to the approach, see also Jakobs (2014, 415–424). A general overview can also be found in Cancio Meliá (2011). For a deep and persuasive critique, see Greco (2010).

  51. On this, see Jakobs (2004b, 44): “Anyone who does not allow himself to be forced under a bourgeois constitution may be forced to separate, whereby at this point, with regard to the question of the legitimacy of risk-based measures, it should be the same whether the enemy is thrown out of the country or thrown into preventive detention for lack of a possibility of expulsion from the country”.

  52. Jakobs (2004a, 90–92). In the same sense, see Joppke (2018, 184): “International terrorists are not criminals but warriors – they don’t want to be ‘reintegrated’. The liberal state should acknowledge their claim, eye to eye, by taking away from them what they have factually renounced and even wish to destroy”.

  53. See, e.g., Ohana (2010, 727–741).

  54. Duff (2011, 146–147), Silva Sánchez (2017, 3–10). On the terrorist as an enemy combatant, see Pawlik (2008).

  55. Some accounts rest precisely on this argument to explain any criminal punishment; see, e.g., Morris (1991). For a recent attempt to rehabilitate a rights forfeiture account, see Wellman (2017, 12–42).

  56. Dubber (2010, 200–215).

  57. For further discussion, see Lacey (1988, 171–181), Duff (2018, 185–201), and Pawlik (2017, 35–46). On criminal law as a republican practice, see also Pettit (1997), Dagger (2011, 59–64).

  58. Lacey (1988, 171–173), Du Bois-Pedain (2017). I am, of course, aware that legitimacy of denationalization can also be denied on the basis of classical liberal conceptions. See an attempt in Gibney (2013b, 651–652). I do believe, however, that, from the political philosophy perspective accepted here, it is simpler to explain why citizenship deprivation should not be taken into consideration under any circumstances. On this same opinion, see Aleinikoff (1986, 1494–1498).

  59. Citizenship co-determines in general the individual identity of a person in the same way that the state is configured and determined by the sum of some citizens who, to a great extent, do not choose freely either. See, on this view, Aleinikoff (1986, 1494).

  60. See Shachar (2012, 1005). Arguing critically against citizenship as an ascribed right by birth, see also Shachar (2009). It is true that a minimal percentage of citizens, Shachar (2012, 1005) states 3%, are able to gain a new citizenship post-birth through migration and naturalization. To the extent that these citizens retain their nationality of origin, which is not always possible, they are called upon to undergo denationalization in a primary way. My argument, however, is not valid here because these are subjects who do commit themselves freely to their new states. Although it is true that the thesis of relinquishment is stronger here, the denationalization of the nationalized is equally illegitimate. Accepting the citizenship deprivation of the nationalized implies the creation of two qualitative levels of citizenship: a real (first-class) citizenship and a provisional (second-class) one. This discrimination is hardly justifiable and offends the idea that citizenship, as the grounding principle of state membership, simply ought to be a status that admits of no gradations. For more on this, see Gibney (2019, 10–16). However, although nationalized individuals effectively consent at first, the bond usually becomes organic over time, which also co-determines the identity of the nationalized citizen. In fact, the candidate for nationalization is not only required to have resided in the country for a period of time or to be committed to the law but also to have assumed the fundamental values (cultural and political) of the country (citizenship tests). See on this Shachar (2012, 1013). Here, too, we are not faced with yet another synallagmatic contract but rather with a deep and essential relationship for the life project of the nationalized citizen.

  61. On what is wrong with the marketization of citizenship, see Shachar (2018, 2017, 804–810).

  62. Duff (2009, 15): although he leaves the door open for the terrorist to be treated as a combatant.

  63. See Duff (2018, 141).

  64. Aleinikoff (1986, 1495). Something different, however, might apply in cases where someone has a second citizenship without any material link with the state in question. This formal relationship is contrary to the principle of the “genuine connection” (International Court of Justice: Nottebohm (Liechtenstein v. Guatemala) 1955), regulating nationality in international law, and the withdrawal in such cases could in certain circumstances be legitimate to the extent that a formal fiction of citizenship is simply nullified. Expatriation would constitute neither a great erosion of citizen rights nor an attack on the identity of the affected person qua citizen. In fact, it is common for non-resident citizens to have fewer civic and political rights; for example, they do not have the right to vote or the social service provision. See, however, Lenard (2018, 107–110), who does not accept citizenship deprivation even in these limited cases.

  65. On this point, see Duff (2018, 141, 192–196).

  66. For a largely persuasive case for that point, see Silva Sánchez (2018, 215–241).

  67. For further argument, see Aleinikoff (1986, 1496), Gibney (2017, 374–375), Lenard (2018, 106–107).

  68. Voltaire (1836, 128).

  69. On this argument, see Carey (2018, 906–908). Barry and Ferracioli’s thesis (2016, 1065–1070) that denationalization is legitimate when an act of terrorism is supported by the second state that is to receive the terrorist after expulsion overcomes this last objection. However, even in this case, the citizen is deprived against his will of a fundamental part of his identity, which cannot be justified from an integrative republican perspective such as that defended here.

  70. An additional problem with the admission of expatriation of terrorists is the risk of contamination (slippery slope). On this, see, e.g., Cancio Meliá (2011, 120–122). Whoever admits the denationalization of the terrorist, especially because of its supposed preventive force, will have a hard time explaining why not to expatriate the murderer or rapist, who is at high risk of recidivism.

  71. Chiao (2019, 182–210). Regarding the collateral consequences, in this same direction, see Chin (2012, 1825–1832).

  72. In this sense, see Gross (2003, 60). See also Zedner (2013, 53, 2007).

  73. For other prominent safeguards applicable to criminal cases under the ECHR, see Trechsel (2005), Campbell/Ashworth/Redmayne (2019, 34–36).

  74. See also Gross, (2003, 68–71). On the substantive approach by the Strasbourg Court to the notion of “penalty” in Art. 7 ECHR and the prohibition of the retroactive imposition of formally non-criminal measures, see Ashworth/Zedner (2010, 76).

  75. In cases in which the terrorist is prosecuted for committing criminal offences, it could also be considered whether denationalization is a measure that would violate the double jeopardy clause (non bis in idem). The answer to this question deserves further investigation, which cannot be carried out in this article. Whoever admits the legitimacy of denationalization will have to fundamentally explore the coincidence between its foundation and that of criminal punishment. If they coincide, both measures cannot be applied cumulatively. On protection against double jeopardy, see Trechsel (2005, 381–402).

  76. For a full discussion, see Gross (2003, 68–71).

  77. See, e.g., Zedner (2016a, 7, 11–12).

  78. See further Trechsel (2005, 81–116).

  79. For discussion, see Davis (2016).

References

  • Aleinikoff, Alexander T. (1986), “Theories of Loss of Citizenship”. Michigan Law Review 84(7): 1471–1503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, Andrew/Zedner, Lucia. (2014), Preventive Justice. Oxford University Press.

  • Ashworth, Andrew/Zedner, Lucia. (2010), “Preventive Orders: A Problem of Undercriminalization?” In: Duff/Farmer/Marshall/Renzo/Tadros (Ed.), The Boundaries of the Criminal Law. Oxford University Press, 59–87.

  • Ball, W. David. (2011), “The Civil Case at the Heart of Criminal Procedure”. American Journal of Criminal Law 38(2): 117–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, Christian/Ferracioli, Luara. (2016), “Can Withdrawing Citizenship Be Justified?” Political Studies 64(4): 1055–1070.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, Christopher. (2016), “Penal Disenfranchisement”. Criminal Law and Philosophy 10(3): 411–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, Liz/Ashworth, Andrew/Redmayne, Mike. (2019), The Criminal Process. Fifth Edition. Oxford University Press.

  • Cancio Meliá, Manuel. (2011), “Terrorism and Criminal Law: The Dream of Prevention, the Nightmare of the Rule of Law”. New Criminal Law Review 14(1): 108–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cancio Meliá, Manuel/Petzsche, Anneke. (2013), “Terrorism as a Criminal Offence”. In: Masferrer/Walker (Eds.), Counter-Terrorism, Human Rights and the Rule of Law. Cheltenham, Northampton, 87–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, Brian. (2018), “Against the Right to Revoke Citizenship”. Citizenship Studies 22(8): 897–911.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheh, Mary M. (1991), “Constitutional Limits on Using Civil Remedies to Achieve Criminal Law Objectives”. Hastings Law Journal 42(5): 1325–1413.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiao, Vincent. (2019), Criminal Law in the Age of the Administrative State. Oxford University Press.

  • Chin, Gabriel J. (2012), “The New Civil Death: Rethinking Punishment in the Era of Mass Conviction”. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 160: 1789–1833.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cloots, Elke. (2017), “The Legal Limits of Citizenship Deprivation as a Counterterror Strategy”. European Public Law 23(1): 57–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Elizabeth F. (2016), “When Democracies Denationalize: The Epistemological Case against Revoking Citizenship”. Ethics & International Affairs 30(2): 253–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dagger, Richard. (2011), “Republicanism and the Foundations of Criminal Law”. In: Duff/Green (Eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law. Oxford University Press, 44–66.

  • Davis, Jeffrey. (2016), “Uncloaking Secrecy: International Human Rights Law in Terrorism Cases”. Human Rights Quarterly 38(1): 58–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Du Bois-Pedain, Antje. (2017), “Punishment as an Inclusonary Practice: Sentencing in a Liberal Constitutional State”. In: Du Bois-Pedain/Ulväng/Asp (Eds.), Criminal Law and the Authority of the State. Hart Publishing, 199–228.

  • Dubber, Markus D. (2010), “Citizenship and Penal Law”. New Criminal Law Review 13(2): 190–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. Antony. (2018), The Realm of Criminal Law. Oxford University Press.

  • Duff, R. Antony. (2011), “Responsibility, Citizenship, and Criminal Law”. In: Duff/Green (Eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law. Oxford University Press, 125–148.

  • Duff, R. Antony. (2010), “A Criminal Law for Citizens”. Theoretical Criminology 14(3): 293–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. Antony. (2009), Answering for Crime. Responsibility and Liability in the Criminal Law. Hart Publishing.

  • Duff, R. Antony. (2003), “Inclusion, Exclusion and the Criminal Law”. Policy Futures in Education 1(4): 699–715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. Antony. (2001), Punishment, Communication, and Community. Oxford University Press.

  • Duff, R. Antony. (1998), “Inclusion and Exclusion: Citizens, Subjects and Outlaws”. Current Legal Problems 51(1): 241–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esbrook, Leslie. (2016), “Citizenship Unmoored: Expatriation as a Counter-Terrorism Tool”. University of Pennsylvania Journal of International Law 37(4): 1275–1329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibney, Matthew J. (2019), “Denationalisation and Discrimination”. Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 45: 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibney, Matthew J. (2017), “Denationalization”. In: Shachar/Bauböck/Bloemraad/Vink (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Citizenship. Oxford University Press, 360–379.

  • Gibney, Matthew J. (2013a), “Deportation, Crime, and the Changing Character of Membership in the United Kingdom”. In: Aas/Bosworth (Eds.), The Borders of Punishment: Migration, Citizenship, and Social Exclusion. Oxford University Press, 218–236.

  • Gibney, Matthew J. (2013b), “Should Citizenship Be Conditional? The Ethics of Denationalization?” Journal of Politics 75(3): 646–658.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, Luís. (2015), Strafprozesstheorie und materielle Rechtskraft. Grundlagen und Dogmatik des Tatbegriffs, des Strafklageverbrauchs und der Wiederaufnahme im Strafverfahrensrecht. Duncker & Humblot.

  • Greco, Luís. (2010), Feindstrafrecht. Nomos.

  • Gross, Emanuel. (2003), “Defensive Democracy: Is It Possible to Revoke the Citizenship, Deport, or Negate the Civil Rights of a Person Instigating Terrorist Action against His Own State?” UMKC Law Review 72(51): 51–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husak, Douglas. (2013), “Preventive Detention as Punishment?” In: Ashworth/Zedner/Tomlin (Eds.), Prevention and the Limits of the Criminal Law. Oxford University Press, 178–193.

  • Jakobs, Günther. (2019), “Feindstrafrecht”. In: Bruns/Gumpp/Mommsen/Nguyen (Ed.), TerrorVon der (Ohn-)Macht des Staates und der Rechtmäßigkeit von Handlungsalternativen. Mohr Siebeck, 71–78.

  • Jakobs, Günther. (2014), “On the Theory of Enemy Criminal Law”. In: Dubber (Ed.), Foundational Texts in Modern Criminal Law. Oxford University Press, 415–424.

  • Jakobs, Günther. (2004a), “Bürgerstrafrecht und Feindstrafrecht”. HHRS März 5(3): 88–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jakobs, Günther. (2004b), Staatliche Strafe: Bedeutung und Zweck. Verlag Ferdinand Schöningh.

  • Joppke, Christian. (2018), “Terrorists Repudiate Their Own Citizenship”. In: Bauböck (Ed.), Debating Transformations of National Citizenship. Springer. 181–184.

  • Joppke, Christian. (2016), “Terror and the Loss of Citizenship”. Citizenship Studies 20(6–7): 728–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingston, Rebecca. (2005), “The Unmaking of Citizens: Banishment and the Modern Citizenship Regime in France”. Citizenship Studies 9(1): 23–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kleinfeld, Joshua. (2016), “Two Cultures of Punishment”. Stanford Law Review 68(5): 933–1036.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, Nicola. (1988), State Punishment: Political Principles and Community Values. Routledge.

  • Lavi, Shai. (2011), “Citizenship Revocation as Punishment: On the Modern Duties of Citizens and Their Criminal Breach”. University of Toronto Law Journal 61(4): 783–810.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lavi, Shai. (2010), “Punishment and the Revocation of Citizenship in the United Kingdom, United States, and Israel”. New Criminal Law Review 13(2): 404–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenard, Patti Tamara. (2018), “Democratic Citizenship and Denationalization”. American Political Science Review 112(1): 99–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenard, Patti Tamara. (2016), “Democracies and the Power to Revoke Citizenship”. Ethics & International Affairs 30(1): 73–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macklin, Audrey. (2018), “The Return of Banishment: Do the New Denationalisation Policies Weaken Citizenship?” In: Bauböck (Ed.), Debating Transformations of National Citizenship. Springer, 163–172.

  • Macklin, Audrey. (2014), “Citizenship Revocation, the Privilege to Have Rights and the Production of the Alien”. Queen’s Law Journal 40(1): 1–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mantu, Sandra. (2018), “‘Terrorist’ Citizens and the Human Right to Nationality”. Journal of Contemporary European Studies 26(1): 28–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mantu, Sandra. (2015), Contingent Citizenship. The Law and Practice of Citizenship Deprivation in International, European and National Perspectives. Brill.

  • Morris, Christopher M. (1991), “Punishment and Loss of Moral Standing”. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21(1): 53–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ohana, Daniel. (2010), “Trust, Distrust and Reassurance: Diversion and Preventive Orders Through the Prism of Feindstrafrecht”. The Modern Law Review 73(5): 721–751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pawlik, Michael. (2017), Normbestätigung und Identitätsbalance. Über die Legitimation staatlichen Strafens. Nomos.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pawlik, Michael. (2008), Der Terrorist und sein Recht: zur rechtstheoretischen Einordnung des modernen Terrorismus. Beck.

  • Pettit, Philip. (1997), “Republican Theory and Criminal Punishment”. Utilitas 9(1): 59–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pillai, Sangeetha/Williams, George. (2017), “Twenty-First Century Banishment: Citizenship Stripping in Common Law Nations”. International and Comparative Law Quarterly 66(3): 522–555.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Puente Rodríguez, Leopoldo. (2019), “Consecuencias de carácter procesal del ‘fraude de etiquetas’: especial referencia a la libertad vigilada”. Revista General de Derecho Procesal 47: 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ristroph, Alice. (2008), “State Intentions and the Law of Punishment”. Journal of Criminal Law & Criminology 98(4): 1353–1406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robles Planas, Ricardo. (2007), “‘Sexual Predators’. Estrategias y límites del Derecho penal de la peligrosidad”. InDret 4: 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shachar, Ayelet. (2018), “The Marketization of Citizenship in an Age of Restrictionism”. Ethics & International Affairs 31(1): 3–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shachar, Ayelet. (2017), “Citizenship for Sale?” In: Shachar/Bauböck/Bloemraad/Vink (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Citizenship. Oxford University Press, 789–816.

  • Shachar, Ayelet. (2012), “Citizenship”. In: Rosenfeld/Sajó (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Constitutional Law. Oxford University Press, 1002–1019.

  • Shachar, Ayelet. (2009), The Birthright Lottery. Harvard University Press.

  • Scheffler, Samuel. (2006), “Is Terrorism Morally Distinctive?” Journal of Political Philosophy 14(1): 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silva Sánchez, Jesús-María. (2018), Malum passionis. Mitigar el dolor del Derecho penal. Atelier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silva Sánchez, Jesús-María. (2017), “Asesinatos selectivos en la ‘guerra punitiva’ contra el terrorismo”. InDret 1: 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiker, Carol S. (1998), “The Limits of the Preventive State”. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 88(3): 771–808.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trechsel, Stefan. (2005), Human Rights in Criminal Proceedings. Oxford University Press.

  • Tripkovic, Milena. (2019), Punishment and Citizenship. A Theory of Criminal Disenfranchisement. Oxford University Press.

  • Voltaire, François Marie Arouet. (1836), A Philosophical Dictionary. Volume I. Kneeland (Ed.). J.Q. Adams.

  • Von Hirsch, Andrew/Wasik, Martin. (1997), “Civil Disqualifications Attending Conviction: A Suggested Conceptual Framework”. Cambridge Law Journal 56(3): 599–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, Christopher Heath. (2017), Rights Forfeiture and Punishment. Oxford University Press.

  • Zaibert, Leo. (2008), “Uprootedness as (Cruel and Unusual) Punishment”. New Criminal Law Review 11(3): 384–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zedner, Lucia. (2019a), “The Hostile Border: Crimmigration, Counter-Terrorism, or Crossing the Line on Rights?” New Criminal Law Review 22(3): 318–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zedner, Lucia. (2019b), “Curtailing citizenship rights as counterterrorism”. In: Goold/Lazarus (Eds.), Security and Human Rights. Hart Publishing, 99–124.

  • Zedner, Lucia. (2016a), “Citizenship Deprivation, Security and Human Rights”. European Journal of Migration and Law 18(2): 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zedner, Lucia. (2016b), “Penal Subversions: When Is a Punishment Not Punishment, Who Decides and on What Grounds?” Theoretical Criminology 20(1): 3–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zedner, Lucia. (2013), “Is the Criminal Law Only for Citizens”. In: Aas/Bosworth (Eds.), The Borders of Punishment: Migration, Citizenship, and Social Exclusion. Oxford University Press, 40–57.

  • Zedner, Lucia. (2007), “Seeking Security by Eroding Rights”. In: Goold/Lazarus (eds.), Security and Human Rights. Brill, 257–275.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am most grateful to Jesús-María Silva Sánchez, Michael Pawlik, and Cristian Irarrázaval for their helpful comments and suggestions. Work on this article was supported by the Alexander-von-Humboldt Foundation and the Ministry of Science, Innovation and Universities of Spain [Grant number: I + D DER2017-82232-P (AEI/FEDER, UE)].

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ivó Coca-Vila.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Coca-Vila, I. Our “Barbarians” at the Gate: On the Undercriminalized Citizenship Deprivation as a Counterterrorism Tool. Criminal Law, Philosophy 14, 149–167 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-019-09517-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-019-09517-5

Keywords

Navigation